Donnerstag, 18. Mai 2023

Edward Feser and the Perverted Faculty Argument: A Critical Anthology

Overview of the Perverted Faculty Argument

The perverted faculty argument asserts that the sole morally permissible use of the sexual faculty is within non-contracepted heterosexual acts between married spouses. Any deviation from this use is considered contrary to the faculty's inherent purpose and, therefore, constitutes a perversion. This perspective is elaborated in sources such as the Faith Magazine article on sexual morality, which outlines the argument's foundational principles.

Key Critiques of the Argument

Questioning the Moral Relevance of Biological Functions

Paul J. Weithman, in Natural Law, Morality, and Sexual Complementarity, challenges the moral significance of biological functions:
"It is hard to see why facts about the natural functions of the reproductive organs are even morally relevant, let alone morally decisive. To suppose they are morally decisive is to suppose that there can be cases in which the intentions of agents are irrelevant to the moral worth of an act. It is to repose the moral worth of those acts in their physical properties."

Emphasis on Intention Over Physical Acts

Arthur Schopenhauer, in The Two Fundamental Problems of Ethics, emphasizes the primacy of intention:
"The intention alone decides on the worth or unworth of the deed, which is why the same deed, according to its intention, can be reprehensible or praiseworthy."

Challenges to Deductive Rigor

Catholic moral philosopher John Montgomery Cooper, as quoted by Leslie Woodcock Tentler in Catholics and Contraception: An American History, questions the deductive rigor of the natural law argument:
"Just precisely how are we going to formulate such a definition of the natural function of the reproductive faculty as will permit relations in pregnancy and sterility and yet bar contraceptive practices? And after we have succeeded—if we succeed—in so formulating this function, just precisely what concrete objective evidence are we going to muster to show that our formulation, and no other, represents the true function?"

Alexander Pavuk, in Catholic Birth Control?, reinforces this critique:
"Cooper targeted the deductive 'perverted faculty' argument by saying that Catholic authorities have offered 'facile assumptions' in place of 'objective evidence' as to 'what precisely is the natural function of the faculty (sex) under consideration?'"

Robin Gill, in A Textbook of Christian Ethics, further contends:
"Even if it is conceded that procreation is the obvious function of sexuality, it is far from clear that it should be the only, or the indispensable, function of human sexuality."

Contextual Variability of Natural Functions

A central question arises: Can a natural faculty possess distinct primary purposes depending on context or circumstances? Might varying situations yield different obligatory ends, with a purpose mandatory in one scenario becoming optional in another? Thomists must demonstrate why such contextual variability is definitively impossible.

Agustín Fuentes, in Race, Monogamy, and Other Lies They Told You, notes:
"Our sexual pair bonding, like our sexual activity, is not limited to reproduction. [...] Even in our closest evolutionary relatives, the apes, it is only recently that we have come to realize that sexual behavior is common, not always related to reproduction, and complicated."

Peter Vardy, in The Puzzle of Ethics, questions functional assignments:
"For instance, is the purpose of a mouth for eating or for kissing or for both? Who is to decide? If kissing is part of the function of mouths, then kissing would become a good rather than, arguably, an evil. The need to make assumptions which may be challenged is, therefore, implicit in Aquinas’ whole approach and weakens its effectiveness."

Mel Thompson, in Understand Ethics: Teach Yourself, expands on definitional challenges:
"How do you decide what is ‘natural’? Science bases its ‘laws of nature’ on observation, and they claim to be no more than an interpretation of the best available evidence. If something is observed that does not fit in with an established law, then either the observation is inaccurate, or another (as yet unknown) law has unexpectedly come into operation. Our understanding of the way in which nature works is therefore constantly being modified. If this also applies to ‘natural law’ as an ethical theory, then we cannot establish fixed criteria for right and wrong—which was the aim of Aquinas and others who followed this line of thought—because our concept of what is natural, and therefore of ‘final causes’, will always be open to modification. It is natural for someone who is seriously ill to die. Does that mean that one should not interfere with the natural course of a disease by giving medicine? In the natural world, the strongest animals often mate with as many sexual partners as they can, fighting off weaker rivals. Should there be selective breeding among humans? Is monogamy unnatural? These examples suggest that there is no easy way to establish the ‘final cause’ that will enable us to say with certainty that we know exactly what every thing or action is for, or what part it has to play in an overall purposeful scheme of the universe."

Christopher Arroyo, in Natural Goodness, Sex, and the Perverted Faculty Argument, argues:
"The relief of sexual tension, practicing safe sex, greater awareness of one’s sexual preferences, alleviating sexual dysfunction, marital satisfaction, and increased self-esteem are all genuine human needs in the human life-form, none of which (except perhaps the first) are needs in other species of animal. These needs indicate some of the ways in which human sexual activity, like human eating, is inextricably bound up with the various physical, psychological, social, and cultural features of the human life-form that make the role of human sexual activity enormously different from the role sexual activity plays in other species. These needs also point more generally to why some intrinsically nonprocreative human sexual activity can contribute to human flourishing: given the human life-form, sex for human beings is not merely for reproduction. [...] Feser’s understanding of the natural ends of sexual activity fails to grasp adequately what is unique about the human life form and its corresponding natural good."

Harry J. Gensler, in Ethics: A Contemporary Introduction (Chapter 13), critiques:
"Critics object that it needn’t be wrong to use organs for something other than their primary biological purpose; for example, there’s nothing wrong in using our feet to kick a football. So it needn’t be wrong to use sex organs for something other than their reproductive functions."

Illustrative Examples Highlighting Inconsistencies

Artificial Insemination and Procedural Adherence

Thomas Aquinas's theory influences modern prohibitions, such as the 1987 Vatican Congregation for the Doctrine of the Faith's stance on artificial insemination:
"Homologous artificial insemination within marriage cannot be allowed."

An exception permits semen collection via a perforated condom during intercourse, preserving the form of a natural generative act without impermissible contraception. The act must simulate potential procreation, even if infertile. Uta Ranke-Heinemann, in Eunuchs for the Kingdom of Heaven: Women, Sexuality, and the Catholic Church, observes:
"The supposedly natural act has become the first commandment and it has kept that status even when its original goal, as prescribed by the Church, procreation, cannot be reached at all, and when obtaining semen through masturbation would be just as good a method, or a better one, because it is less complicated. But masturbation still ranks with the most serious, unnatural sins of contraception, even here when it is precisely being used to make conception possible. The standardized procedure has become more important than the goal, namely procreation. What is 'natural' is determined by old traditions, and such traditions are carefully protected by old male celibates."

Natural Family Planning vs. Mechanical Contraception

Natural family planning (NFP), once disallowed by Church Fathers, is now permitted as a contraceptive method among Catholics, while condom use remains sinful. Yet, the intent behind both practices—to avoid conception—is identical. Protestants often view NFP and mechanical contraception as ethically equivalent. As noted, a deity distinguishing morally between these methods would appear overly meticulous, particularly given NFP's superior efficacy per the Pearl Index.

Analysis of Feser's Thomistic Framework

Edward Feser's interpretation of Thomistic natural law employs distinctions between actions "contrary to" and "other than" natural ends. To enhance systematic coherence, one might incorporate "in accordance with" as a complementary term: actions contrary to nature are morally evil, those in accordance with it are morally good, and those other than it are morally neutral.

For instance, eating breakfast or bathing aligns with human nature and is thus morally good. If kissing is a natural function of the mouth and tongue, it too yields moral value. Conversely, obtaining a semen sample via masturbation for medical purposes (e.g., cancer diagnosis or infertility assessment) would be morally evil as contrary to nature. Chewing gum exemplifies moral neutrality: it uses the digestive system differently from its primary function, without direct contravention, despite potential futility or strain.

However, Feser's distinction between "contrary to" and "other than" remains elusive. In both, the natural end is deliberately avoided, yet only the former incurs moral evil. Even John Skalko, an intellectual ally in Disordered Actions, finds it untenable:
"Feser relies upon an unclear account of contrary use and other than use, which is either ad hoc or cannot grant him the conclusion he desires."

If this distinction collapses, Feser's natural law framework falters: either innocuous acts like chewing gum or hand-walking become morally wrong, or previously condemned actions revert to moral neutrality.

Analogies Illustrating Inconsistencies in Natural Function

David Bradshaw, in What Does it Mean to be Contrary to Nature?, questions the consistency of deeming certain uses "contrary" to nature:
"Presumably, the natural function of the ambulatory system is locomotion. Does not one who walks on a treadmill use this system in a way contrary to its natural function? Walking on a treadmill seems a rather precise parallel to having sex with a condom, for it involves performing the very act of walking while ensuring that its natural result, movement from one place to another does not occur. Or consider the respiratory faculty. Presumably, its natural function is to deliver oxygen to the bloodstream. People (or boys, at any rate) often enjoy inhaling helium because of the way it makes their voices absurdly high-pitched. Is this an unnatural use of the respiratory faculty? One might answer that it is not, because on the next breath they can always go back to inhaling normal air. But of course the same can be said of masturbation; it too uses a natural faculty for something other than its natural end without in any way preventing that faculty from performing its natural function the next time it is used."

The Is-Ought Distinction and Normative Derivations

David Hume's is-ought problem posits that prescriptive moral claims cannot logically follow from descriptive facts alone. Kai Nielsen, in Atheism and Philosophy, articulates:
"Natural moral law theorists confuse talking about what is the case with talking about what ought to be the case. They confuse de jure statements with de facto statements. A statement about what people or what normal people seek, strive for or desire is a factual, non-normative statement. From this statement or from any conjunction of such statements alone no normative (de jure) conclusions can be validly deduced except in such trivial cases as from 'He wears black shoes' one can deduce 'He wears black shoes or he ought to be a priest.' But this simply follows from the conventions governing the disjunction 'or.' Moreover, because it is a disjunction it is not actually action-guiding; it is not actually normative. To discover what our natural inclinations are is simply to discover a fact about ourselves; to discover what purposes we have is simply to discover another fact about ourselves, but that we ought to have these inclinations or purposes or that it is desirable that we have them does not follow from statements asserting that people have such and such inclinations or purposes. These statements can very well be true but no moral or normative conclusions follow from them."

David Bentley Hart, in Is, Ought, and Nature’s Laws from A Splendid Wickedness and Other Essays, elaborates:
"Even if one could exhaustively describe the elements of our nature, the claim that we are morally obliged to act in accord with them, or to prefer 'natural' uses to 'unnatural,' could be made only as something additional and adventitious to the whole ensemble of facts that this description would comprise. Otherwise we could not see it as a moral good at all, but only as a negotiable feature of private taste. The assumption that the natural and moral orders are connected to one another in any but a purely pragmatic way must be of its nature antecedent to our experience of the world. I know of many stout defenders of natural law who are quick to dismiss Hume’s argument, but who—when pressed to explain themselves—can do no better than to resort to a purely conditional argument: if one is (for instance) to live a fully human life, one must then . . . (etc.). But, in supplementing a dubious 'is' with a negotiable 'if,' one certainly cannot arrive at a morally categorical 'ought.'"

Hart further critiques Edward Feser's defense in Nature Loves to Hide from the same volume:
"The most gallant of Feser’s non sequiturs is his claim that, because reason necessarily seeks the good, there exists no gap into which any Humean distinction between facts and values can insinuate itself. But obviously the gap lies in the dynamic interval between (in the terms of Maximus the Confessor) the 'natural' and 'gnomic' wills. The venerable principle that the natural will is a pure ecstasy toward the good means that, at the level of gnomic deliberation, whatever we will we desire as the good, but not that philosophical theory can by itself prove which facts imply which values, or that the good must naturally be understood as an incumbent 'ought' rather than a compelling 'I want.' Feser asserts that 'purely philosophical arguments' can establish 'objective true moral conclusions.' And yet, curiously enough, they never, ever have. That is a bedtime story told to conjure away the night’s goblins, like the Leibnizian fable of the best possible world or the philosophe’s fairy tale about the plain dictates of reason."

An anonymous commentator notes:
"Feser claims that he does not have an 'is-ought' problem. Maybe so, but he has merely replaced it with a 'nature’s End - ought' problem that is equally tenacious. He still faces the question of 'So nature intends that I X. But why should I X?' Seems to me he has gained nothing from that move."

Sources of Normativity and the Role of Will

Critics argue that normative obligations stem from wills—either one's own or another's—rather than impersonal natural facts. In German linguistic analysis, the verb "sollen" (ought/should) implies a personal agent demanding action. For example, a doctor's prescription creates an "ought" based on their directive. Natural faculties, however, lack this personal agency, rendering them incapable of generating moral imperatives.

If natural law invokes God as the demanding will, this raises issues of divine communication. A philosophical skeptic, influenced by Hume or Fritz Mauthner (as cited in On Fritz Mauthner's Critique of Language by Gershon Weiler), might view natural "laws" as human projections:
"The so-called 'laws' of the natural sciences originate in man's preference for order, but not from nature itself. There is nothing corresponding to them in nature. The same criticism applies to the concept of 'aim' in nature, which M[authner] takes, with Spinoza, to be only an analogy to human intention."

Mel Thompson, in Understand Ethics: Teach Yourself, emphasizes:
"To get an absolute command (or ‘categorical imperative’, as we shall see later) you have to presuppose someone who gives that command. Within the natural law theory, as it has developed since the time of Aquinas, that ‘someone’ is God. This gives its moral pronouncements an authority that may not be justified by the logic on which the argument is based."

L.A. Rollins, in The Myth of Natural Rights, suggests natural law often masks personal preferences:
"As I’ve said, natural laws and natural rights are inventions intended to advance the interests of the inventors (whom I shall call 'natural legislators'). What is often involved is an attempt to manipulate other people into behaving as desired by a natural legislator, by duping them into accepting the values of the natural legislator as the values of nature. Thus, the personal, subjective preferences of a natural legislator are passed off as the impersonal, objective requirements of nature. For example, Frederick D. Wilhelmsen writes that, 'Natural law insists that pornography … is bad and that it is bad not just for me, but for everybody, and it equally insists that not only must I not invade my neighbor’s property but that he must not invade mine or anybody else’s.' In other words, Frederick Wilhelmsen insists that pornography is bad for everybody, and he equally insists that no one must invade anybody else’s property. But in order to give his personal preferences greater authority, Wilhelmsen pretends that it is nature who is doing all the insisting."

Alternative normativity arises from personal goals (hypothetical imperatives), as in: "I want to be home at ten o'clock, so I must take the bus at half past nine." Thompson notes a parallel in Eastern philosophy:
"In Eastern philosophy, the idea of karma—that actions have consequences that cumulatively influence the future—relates the state of the world to moral choices. But this gives only a 'hypothetical' command (in other words, one that says 'If you want to achieve X, then you must do Y'), not an absolute moral command."

Elective Priorities and Hierarchical Values

David Bentley Hart, in Is, Ought, and Nature’s Laws, addresses the challenge of prioritizing values:
"Elective priorities. Assume, however, that we can establish the existence of a moral imperative implicit in the orderliness of the world, as perceived by a rational will that, for itself, must seek the good: Does that assure that we can prove what hierarchy of values follows from this, or how we should calculate the relative preponderance of diverse moral ends? Yes, we may all agree that murder is worse than rudeness; but, beyond the most rudimentary level of ethical deliberation, pure logic proves insufficient as a guide to which ends truly command our primary obedience, and our arguments become ever more dependent upon prior evaluations and preferences that, as far as philosophy can discern, are culturally or psychologically contingent. Consistent natural law cases can be made for or against slavery, for example, or for or against capital punishment, depending on which values one has privileged at a level too elementary for philosophy to adjudicate. At some crucial point, natural law argument, pressed to disclose its principles, dissolves into sheer assertion."

Theological and Denominational Dependencies

Thomistic natural law is inherently tied to Catholic theology. Without belief in God and Church teachings, it lacks grounding. Mark D. Jordan, in The Ethics of Sex, affirms:
"[...] Thomas knew as well as any medieval theologian that human societies disagree sharply about how human beings ought to act. He himself mentions cases in which whole societies teach their members to do things that he thinks contrary to natural law. Given the diversity of societies, the contradictions in the history of moral conventions, is there any kernel of natural law that every human being shares? Perhaps there is, but that kernel will not be enough to direct us individually or to make us agree collectively. In practical matters, agreement about principles and about the shape of moral reasoning is no guarantee of agreement about practical conclusions. Indeed, the more particular the case, the more difficult it is to arrive at a conclusion on which all will agree. Alternately, the more specific a norm or precept proposed in ethics or law, the more liable it is to justified exception. In many particular cases, the right course of action cannot be regularly agreed, even among virtuous people. This insufficiency of natural law becomes the starting point for Thomas's arguments in the Summa on the need for divine law, that is, for an explicit teaching about human conduct revealed by God. Because natural law participates in God's eternal plan only 'according to the proportion of the capacity of human nature,' God generously teaches a more articulate law, the divine law that is eminently contained in the Old and New Testaments. We are able to 'fulfill' the natural law only after God's revelation. The content of natural law only becomes clear with the handing down of the Old Law, the law of Moses. The content of natural law only becomes practicable with the gift of grace in the New Law—whether we are talking about justice or about 'unnatural' sex. Many of the 'natural law' arguments we hear today do not rise to the level of misreadings of Aquinas. They are rather loud assertions pretending to be common sense or, what is worse, natural science. But even in more serious efforts to make 'natural law' arguments against certain sexual acts, we can hear how easily Christian theology can slip from rich conceptions of law as divine self-disclosure to poor conceptions of law as imposed ideology or criminal code. [...] The difficulty we now feel in speaking convincing arguments about 'unnatural' sex cannot be blamed on just the growth of modern medicine or the spread of liberal notions about self-fulfillment. We understand it better as a loss of the grand Christian rhetorics within which sin-identities made sense of acts by organizing them. When we try to pull the acts away from the identities, we find that they don't make much sense. Of course they don't. They never did without identities. This loss of coherence in specifying 'unnatural' acts is closely connected to the loss of conviction produced by appeals to natural law. Christian condemnations of unnatural acts were not meant to work without Christian sin-identities; arguments from natural law were not meant to work outside of an ideal pedagogy of virtuous family, just city, and luminous divine revelation. Natural law arguments about sex are not detachable from the Christian narrative of a progressive divine teaching through history."

This dependency traces to patristic views on Eden, as noted by Reddit user Quidfacis_:
"It might help to read Aquinas and Augustine's take on progeneration in the Garden of Eden to understand why, historically, the sexual members have such specific functions. The predominant view of the time was that either there would have been no procreation, or procreation would have occurred through some divine means. This because sexuality is bound up with lust, and lust is naughty. Aquinas and Augustine argue against the view by claiming that sex would have recurred without stirring the loins through lust."

Evolutionary and Contextual Challenges to Thomistic Natural Law

The Impact of Evolution on Fixed Purposes

Thomistic natural law presupposes fixed essences and purposes derived from reason's interpretation of final causes. However, this framework encounters difficulties when confronted with modern understandings of evolution, constant change, and contextual variability in natural functions.

Mel Thompson, in Understand Ethics: Teach Yourself: Making Sense of the Morals of Everyday Living, articulates:
"If the whole world is in a state of constant change; if galaxies are moving outwards towards an unknown future; if stars are born and die, and planets spinning around them are vulnerable to their death and many other cosmic accidents; if life on planet Earth is a recent phenomenon and subject to a process of evolution – how can the purpose or goal of anything be fixed? The natural law approach is based on the idea that reason can interpret the essence, purpose and ‘final cause’ of things. We need to consider whether this is compatible with a world viewed from the perspective of evolution and change. Is morality the result of deliberately going against our basic instincts, as suggested by Richard Dawkins at the end of The Selfish Gene: ‘We alone on earth can rebel against the tyranny of the selfish replicators’? Or is some sense of morality genetically programmed into us? Research on the behaviour of apes suggests that there may be the basics of morality – in the attitude of groups to individuals, and the support given by one individual ape to another. So, for example, animals that fight can ‘make up’ afterwards. Is this programmed into them in order to help the species survive in a competitive environment?"

If evolutionary theory holds, organic entities lack metaphysically fixed Aristotelian forms at the species level. For instance, a squirrel's traits result from brutal natural selection, with each generation potentially undergoing alterations that influence successors. Change is inherent to generational continuity. Humanity, having emerged through an amoral evolutionary process, cannot be viewed as possessing a timeless metaphysical essence—including assumptions of exclusive heterosexuality—as an ethical template. Nature's fluidity in evolution contrasts sharply with natural law's rigidity, rendering the latter unsuitable as a stable moral standard. Evolution encompasses not only physical forms but also behaviors and inclinations, necessitating their inclusion in any assessment of biological functionalities.

David Bentley Hart, in Is, Ought, and Nature’s Laws from A Splendid Wickedness and Other Essays, further critiques:
"Even if final causality in nature is demonstrable, does it yield moral knowledge if there is no clear moral analogy between natural ends and the proper objects of human motive? For Thomas Aquinas, only a moral disorder can make one claim ignorance of the reality of the God who, as the source of one’s being, is supremely worthy of love. True in principle, of course. Even so, the 'failure' to find a moral dimension in one’s intrinsic ontological contingency may not be entirely culpable. Our modern narrative of nature is of an order shaped by immense ages of monstrous violence: mass extinctions, the cruel profligacy of an algorithmic logic that squanders ten thousand lives to fashion a single durable type, an evolutionary process that advances not despite, but because of, disease, warfare, predation, famine, and so on. And the majestic order thus forged? One of elemental caprice, natural calamity, the mercilessness of chance — injustice thrives, disaster befalls the innocent, and children suffer. Why, our deracinated modern might ask, should we believe that nature’s organizing finality, given the kinds of efficient causes it prompts into action, has moral implications that command imitation, obedience, or (most unlikely of all) love?"

Teleology, Functionality, and Contextual Variability

Thomists posit teleology or final causality as sufficient for natural law ethics. Critics may deny objective teleology outright or argue it is merely necessary but insufficient, leaving room for debate on human specifics. Thomists assume natural entities have a single primary purpose, a dogma traceable to Aristotle, whose view of eternal species constancy influenced biology but conflicts with evolution's emphasis on habitat context.

This dogma may violate Aristotle's principle that human artifacts mirror natural structures ("art imitates nature"). Natural faculties resemble versatile tools, such as a hammer designed for pounding nails but usable for cracking nuts without moral fault. As noted in an analysis from faculty.cbu.ca:
"A hammer may have been designed to pound nails, and it may perform that particular job best. But it is not sinful to employ a hammer to crack nuts if I have no other more suitable tool immediately available. The hammer, being a relatively versatile tool, may be employed in a number of ways. It has no one 'proper' or 'natural' function."

J. L. Ackrill, in Aristotle the Philosopher, observes Aristotle acknowledging dual essential purposes in organs, such as the elephant's trunk for breathing and feeding in swamps, or another case where one job holds higher order. This suggests contextual dependency, contradicting the single-purpose dogma. If organs can serve two equally primary functions, the same may apply to faculties.

Graham Priest, in Sexual Perversion, addresses evolutionary functionality:
"First, it is no part of a modern notion of functionality that a function is unique. Some organ may well be involved in different uses, each of which gives, or has given, its possessor an evolutionary advantage. In particular, then, the mere fact that the genitals are involved in conception does not mean that they do not have other important functions. It is not incredible to suppose that the giving and receiving of pleasure is one of these. [...] Second, and relatedly, behaviour patterns traditionally reckoned as perverse are hardly modern ones. They are long-standing and widely spread through sections of the population. [...] This suggests (though, of course, it by no means proves) that at least some of them may well have been selected for evolutionarily. If such a behaviour pattern is genetically based, this is, presumably, the case. Notoriously, for example, some sociobiologists have argued that homosexuality is a genetic disposition, and that homosexuality makes perfectly good sense as a strategy for facilitating certain gene transmissions. I certainly do not want to endorse the sociobiological account of homosexuality. I mention it simply to demonstrate that in the light of modern science, it makes perfectly good sense for things counted traditionally as perversions to be functional. Third, and again relatedly, according to both accounts that we looked at, a functional trait may cease to give an evolutionary advantage if the environmental context changes: witness the dinosaurs. (According to the dispositional account, the trait in question then ceases to be a function.) Now, one of the most salient features of the current human environment is the imminent threat of over-population and the consequent environmental disaster. Such an event would doubtless have consequences for the human gene pool - possibly even destroying it. Hence, assuming that it is unrealistic for most people to become celibate, increasing non-procreational sexual activity may well be an evolutionarily sensible strategy in the present context."

Priest adds:
"[T]here is nothing wrong per se with using something for other than its Darwinian biological function. For example, whether one gives an aetiological or a dispositional account of function, body hair may plausibly be supposed to have various functions (protection from the sun, holding body-secretions close to the skin). Yet there is nothing wrong with shaving one's head or armpits and using the hair for something else. Similarly, a function of certain body secretions is to form an infection-protective coating for the skin; but there is nothing wrong with washing frequently (and using the secretion-infused result to water the flowers)."

Christopher Hamilton, in Alexander Pruss on Love and the Meaningfulness of Sex, concurs:
"Our organs are not for anything, and they have no function or purpose: they do what they do, well or ill. Still less does the human body have a purpose or function; it is not for anything. That, of course, is one of the conclusions to be drawn from evolutionary theory. [...] In any case, even if we could say unequivocally what the purpose of any given organ is, we cannot conclude that we ought to use it for that purpose, still less that we ought to use it only for that purpose. That just does not follow. If our hands had the purpose of manipulating objects, it would not follow from that that we ought to use them for that or that we ought not to use them for other things. [...] If the sexual organs are for reproduction, it does not follow that they ought to be used for this purpose, not even if we grant that they may or even ought also to be used for other purposes. This no more follows than it follows from the fact (if it is a fact) that human teeth and digestive system are for the consumption of animal flesh (amongst other things) that we ought to eat meat. You cannot refute vegetarianism so easily."

Historical Misconceptions and Holistic Critiques

Natural law's sexual ethics historically rested on outdated views, such as semen containing the full potential person, equating non-procreative acts to near-homicide. Anthony Kenny, in Medieval Philosophy, explains:
"Aquinas is often invoked in contemporary discussions of the morality of contraception and abortion. In fact, he had very little to say on either topic. Contraception is discussed, along with masturbation, in a question in the Summa contra Gentiles concerning ‘the disordered emission of semen’. Aquinas maintains that this is a crime against humanity, second only to homicide. This claim rests on the belief that only the male provides the active element in conception, so that the sperm has an individual history continuous with the embryo, the fetus, and the infant. In fact, of course, male and female gametes contribute equally to the genetic constitution of the eventual human being. An embryo, unlike the father’s sperm or semen, is the same individual organism as an infant at birth. For Aquinas, the emission of semen in circumstances unsuitable for conception was the same kind of thing, on a minor scale of course, as the exposure or starvation of an individual infant. That is why he thought masturbation a poor man’s version of homicide."

Uta Ranke-Heinemann, in Eunuchs for the Kingdom of Heaven: Women, Sexuality, and the Catholic Church, notes:
"For Thomas, every sexual act has to be a marital act, and every marital act has to be an act of procreation. A violation of the sexual commandments is a violation of life itself. For the semen already contains the potential for the whole person (or, more precisely, the whole man, for women come into being only when something goes awry in the process of development; De malo 15 a. 2). The unregulated ejaculation runs counter to the well-being of nature, which lies in the preservation of the species. Therefore, after the sin of murder, through which human nature, which already exists in reality, is destroyed, the sin of preventing the generation of human nature comes in second place (Summa Contra Gentiles III, 122). Contraception is thus not the same thing as murder, but is very close to it. Along with Aristotle, Thomas calls semen 'something divine' (De malo 15, 2)."

Otto Weininger, in Sex and Character: An Investigation of Fundamental Principles, counters:
"[I]t cannot be a moral duty to ensure the continuation of the species, as is so frequently argued. This excuse is such an obviously barefaced lie that I hesitate to make a fool of myself by asking whether any human being has ever performed sexual intercourse with the thought of having to avert the great danger of the demise of humankind, […] and nobody who asks himself sincerely will feel it to be his duty to ensure the continuing existence of the human species. But what is not felt to be a duty is not a duty."

A holistic critique emphasizes viewing humans as psycho-physical unities, not isolated parts. Peter Vardy, in The Puzzle of Ethics, states:
"It may also be argued that Aquinas’ approach is not holistic – it fails to consider the human being as a psycho-physical unit. To separate, for instance, genitalia out as having a particular purpose on their own without considering the whole complexity of a person’s relationship to his or her body, psychology, sexuality in general, the ability of human beings as embodied persons to express and receive love and to come to their full humanity may be a diminution of human beings as people. We are not an accumulation of ‘bits’ – we are whole human persons and all moral judgements must take our complexity as human persons into account."

Melissa Moschella, in Old Natural Law Theory, Marriage, and Sexual Ethics, adds:
"Feser’s argument about sexual ethics makes the mistake of beginning with the ends of one bodily system (the reproductive system) and presuming them to be ends of the person as a whole."

Reconsidering Homosexuality within Natural Law

Even within Old Natural Law, homosexual acts need not be deemed immoral if viewed as natural, akin to animal behaviors, and healthy for practitioners. Otto Weininger observes:
"[I]t is still worth remarking that sexually inverted people can otherwise be perfectly healthy and, apart from accessorial social factors, do not feel worse than all the other healthy people. If one asks them whether they have any wish to be different in this respect, one quite often receives a negative answer."

Dirk Baltzly, in Peripatetic Perversions: A Neo-Aristotelian Account of the Nature of Sexual Perversion, questions:
"I think that perversions, if there are any such things, are either sexual manifestations of various aspects of bad moral character or states that are psychologically inextricable from bad moral character. I am myself unsure whether there are any sexual perversions. […], I am very confident that the psychological generalisations that have underwritten the claim that homosexuality is a perversion are false."

Alan Soble, in Philosophy of Sexuality, asserts:
"Whether a sexual activity is natural or perverted does not depend [...] on what organs are used or where they are put, but only on the character of the psychology of the sexual encounter."

Mel Thompson challenges:
"One might argue that the presence of sexual organs in a human being implies that he or she is designed for sexual activity and the conception of children – in which case, celibacy is as unnatural as homosexuality, since it is a denial of the complete natural function of procreation. If this is established, then it is illogical to accept a celibate partnership between those who are sexually attracted. Some people are naturally attracted by members of the same sex. They experience their feelings as completely natural. Any difficulties that arise are the result of social conditioning, not nature. Sexuality can be said to achieve three ends: 1. physical pleasure 2. the deepening of a relationship 3. the conception of children Only the third end is precluded by homosexual relationships. But is not the search for pleasure and for deep relationships as natural as the conception of children? If a marriage is known to be infertile, are heterosexual acts between its partners therefore immoral simply because conception is impossible Marriage is a social function, and promiscuity can be practised equally by homosexuals and heterosexuals. The fact that homosexual couples cannot marry does not preclude deep and permanent relationships. If a homosexual couple form a stable relationship, they may be able to offer children a home that is, at the very least, as valuable to their upbringing as one in which there is either a single parent, or a heterosexual couple with a bad relationship. Hence, it would seem illogical to discriminate in this matter. In pointing out some of the ways in which the ‘natural law’ view of the homosexual couple’s situation might be challenged, it is not intended to undermine the principle of natural law as such, but to show that there are some areas of morality – particularly where relationships are concerned – where it is difficult to consider morality mainly in terms of specific actions."

Kurt Blankschaen, in Rethinking Same-Sex Sex in Natural Law Theory, proposes:
"Many prominent proponents of Old and New Natural Law morally condemn sexual acts between people of the same sex because those acts are incapable of reproduction; they each offer a distinct set of supporting reasons. While some New Natural Law philosophers have begun to distance themselves from this moral condemnation, there are not many similarly ameliorative efforts within Old Natural Law. I argue for the bold conclusion that Old Natural Law philosophers can accept the basic premises of Old Natural Law without also being committed to morally condemning sexual activity between people of the same sex. I develop an argument from analogy that shows how we can draw metaphysically distinct subcategories based on someone’s capacity to experience the unitive goods of sex. This unitive capacity constitutes the sub-category and provides a distinct principle for evaluating how members of that sub-category (X) act as members of that sub-category, rather than as acting as defective members of another category (Y). Even though my argument is ‘internal’ to Old Natural Law, I conclude by showing how these conclusions can also address some of the objections to same-sex sex in New Natural Law."

Historical Development in Catholic Teaching on Contraception

Catholic doctrine on contraception has evolved, reflecting historicity without complete reversal. Katie Grimes, in Butler Interprets Aquinas: How to Speak Thomistically About Sex, notes:
"When Catholics embrace the essentially eschatological and therefore unfinished character of the process of natural law knowledge, they realize that the reliability of the tradition is neither destroyed nor diminished by its errors. In this way, the discovery of the humanity of homosexuality does not overturn the authority of the man who once condemned it. Heterosexual Catholics need no longer fear the ecclesial inclusion of lesbians and gays while lesbian and gay Catholics need no longer fear the Thomistic texts that have been so expertly used against them. Misrepresented as an author who underwrites magisterial terror, Aquinas reveals himself to be a source of lesbian and gay Catholic empowerment."

John T. Noonan, Jr., in Contraception: A History of Its Treatment by the Catholic Theologians and Canonists, summarizes:
"The recorded statements of Christian doctrine on contraception did not have to be read in a way requiring an absolute prohibition. The doctrine had been molded by the teaching of the Gospels on the sanctity of marriage; the Pauline condemnation of unnatural sexual behavior; the Old Testament emphasis on fertility; the desire to justify marriage while extolling virginity; the need to assign rational purpose and limit to sexual behavior. The doctrine was formed in a society where slavery, slave concubinage, and the inferiority of women were important elements of the environment affecting sexual relations. The education of children was neither universal nor expensive. Underpopulation was a main governmental concern. The doctrine condemning contraception was formulated against the Gnostics, reasserted against the Manichees, and established in canon law at the climax of the campaign against the Cathars. Reaction to these movements hostile to all procreation was not the sole reason for the doctrine, but the emphases, sweep, and place of the doctrine issued from these mortal combats. The environmental changes requiring a reconsideration of the rule accumulated only after 1850. These changes brought about a profound development of doctrine on marriage and marital intercourse: love became established as a meaning and end of the coital act. Before women were emancipated and marriages in the West came to be based on personal decision, writing like that of Von Hildebrand, Doms, Haring, Suenens, Fuchs, Ford, and Kelly would have seemed chimerical. Their work responded to the change in conditions. Their teaching on marriage was in many ways different from that of older theologians. Huguccio would have marveled at the teaching of Ford and Kelly, Jerome would have been astounded at Haring. Suppose the test of orthodoxy were, Would Augustine or Thomas be surprised if he were to return and see what Catholic theologians are teaching today? By this criterion, the entire development on the purposes of marital intercourse would have been unorthodox. But it is a perennial mistake to confuse repetition of old formulas with the living law of the Church. The Church, on its pilgrim's path, has grown in grace and wisdom. That intercourse must be only for a procreative purpose, that intercourse in menstruation is mortal sin, that intercourse in pregnancy is forbidden, that intercourse has a natural position - all these were once common opinions of the theologians and are so no more. Was the commitment to an absolute prohibition of contraception more conscious, more universal, more complete, than to these now obsolete rules? These opinions, now superseded, could be regarded as attempts to preserve basic values in the light of the biological data then available and in the context of the challenges then made to the Christian view of man. At the core of the existing commitment might be found values other than the absolute, sacral value of coitus. Through a variety of formulas, five propositions had been asserted by the Church. Procreation is good. Procreation of offspring reaches its completion only in their education. Innocent life is sacred. The personal dignity of a spouse is to be respected. Marital love is holy. In these propositions the values of procreation, education, life, personality, and love were set forth. About these values a wall had been built; the wall could be removed when it became a prison rather than a bulwark."

Thompson adds:
"Sex within the ‘safe period’ of the woman’s ovulatory cycle is generally permitted in Catholic moral teaching because the failure to conceive at that time is part of nature’s limitation, rather than the result of a direct attempt to do something unnatural."

Noonan elaborates:
"At the most on four days a month is the union of intercourse and fertility normal. If we seek to understand the divine plan from what nature has given humanity, we must infer that it is for a brief part of any life that fertility is intended, and that nature has designed man so that many acts of intercourse will be sterile. […] The reason a sterilizing act is wrong is that it asserts man's dominion over the generative process and effects the disruption of the natural nexus. But when steps are taken to assure that intercourse is not fertile in a period not intended by nature to be fertile, man acts in subordination to the divine plan and does not effect any disruption of the sacred link between love and fertility. Further, the directly intended act is the assurance of natural sterility. [...] But at those times when nature intends no procreation, there is no interference in the structure or signification of the sexual act when means are used increasing the probability that the natural rhythm will hold."

David Bradshaw, in What Does it Mean to be Contrary to Nature?, notes:
"Perhaps most interestingly, a physician who played a leading role in the development of the Pill, John Rock, argued vigorously that the Pill fit comfortably within existing Catholic teaching. He reasoned that since it uses a naturally occurring hormone, progesterone, to extend a woman's infertile period, it is effectively no more than an aid to the rhythm method."

Conclusion

These critiques underscore that Thomistic natural law falters as a standalone philosophical framework, relying instead on unbridgeable logical gaps and ecclesiastical authority for its normative force. The adaptability of Catholic teaching on contraception illustrates natural law's non-static nature, highlighting its responsiveness to new insights and societal changes.

Mittwoch, 17. Mai 2023

Real Death of God Theology

Voices on the Content of this Blog Entry:

Robert Lawrence Kuhn (Closer to Truth):
“Thoughtful and original construction — to me, it shows the immense richness and significance of the issue, even if I don't rank it highly among competing ultimate explanations ;-) — but what do I know?”

Paul Draper (American philosopher, known for work in philosophy of religion):
“While I don't find the deductions convincing, the overall view is interesting. I need to include it in my taxonomy of theisms and deisms. This seems to be the opposite of emergent theism/deism, where the world evolves into or produces God. Here, God devolves or transforms into the world. I'll call it demergent deism.”

Bill Vallicella (Maverick Philosopher blog):
“Mainländer’s ideas are indeed very interesting.”

Joseph Schmid (Majesty of Reason YouTube channel):
“This is fascinating!!”


The Death of God — A Philosophical Reconstruction

In the 1950s and 60s, a movement emerged within theology known as the God-is-dead movement — or theothanatology (from theos, God, and thanatos, death).

I believe the most plausible and coherent interpretation of the idea that God is truly and literally dead can be reconstructed from the pessimistic philosophy of the German thinker Philipp Mainländer (1841–1876) — poet, metaphysician, and radical metaphysical pessimist.

Mainländer advances a provocative thesis: “God is dead, and His death was the life of the world.” This statement, central to his metaphysical system, is articulated in his primary work, The Philosophy of Redemption. The following seven theses, directly quoted from Mainländer, encapsulate his reasoning:

  1. “God willed non-being.

  2. God’s essence was the obstacle to His immediate self-annihilation.

  3. Therefore, His essence had to disintegrate into a multiplicity — a world — in which each individual part strives for non-being.

  4. In this striving, these parts mutually hinder and weaken one another.

  5. God’s entire essence passed into the world, transformed into a finite force.

  6. The universe now has a single objective: non-being, achieved through the gradual dissipation of its total energy.

  7. Each individual will eventually reach a point where its desire for non-being can be fulfilled.”

(Source: synkretic.com/issues/the-philosophy-of-redemption)

Although Mainländer employed an inductive method, deriving principles from outer and inner experience rather than formal deduction, the seven theses quoted above contain a latent logical structure that can be philosophically justified. What follows is a rational framework that reveals the dormant argumentative architecture implicit in his work, reconstructing his ideas into a deductive sequence for analytical clarity.

Even if one does not accept all the premises, I argue they are at least philosophically defensible and plausible.


A Deductive Reconstruction

Deduction 1: God’s Total Transformation

A1. The universe began a finite time ago.
A2. Such a beginning could only have been initiated by an act of God.

B1. Creation ex nihilo is metaphysically incoherent.
(“Saying God can create something from nothing is like claiming you can vomit up a skipped lunch with a powerful enough dry heave.”)
B2. A transformation of a transcendent substance into immanent things, however, is possible.

C1. God is absolutely simple (simplicitas): non-fragmented, motionless, timeless, without parts or internal structure. This view aligns with classical theism (Augustine, Aquinas, Anselm).
C2. Because God has no parts to transform, He must give His whole being in any creative act. In His simplicity, to give a part is to give the whole. He is an undivided “blob” of pure being: take any “part”, and you take everything.

→ D. Therefore, God has completely transformed Himself into the universe.
His infinite being has become finite existence.
His total, transcendent being is now entirely immanent.

Any attempt to resist this conclusion relies on an appeal to mystery, which should only ever be a last resort in philosophy. If the concept of divine simplicity is taken seriously, the transformation thesis becomes the only coherent alternative to creatio ex nihilo, which is itself deeply problematic.


On the Nature of This “Change”

One might argue that if God changed, something of Him must remain the same — a core assumption in Aristotelian metaphysics:

“Aristotle insists that in every change something remains the same.”
J. L. Ackrill, Aristotle the Philosopher

But Mainländer's God is not a substance that merely alters states. He is an absolute unity — indivisible and without internal multiplicity. Therefore, His transformation leaves nothing behind. It is not a change, but a total ontological conversion: from pure transcendence to fragmented immanence.

He doesn't persist through the process — He ceases to exist. What remains is the echo, the reverberation, the broken pieces of that original unity: our world.


God's Radical Otherness

As Duns Scotus put it:

“God is infinite being, creatures are finite beings. Yet both are called ‘being’ in the univocal sense — not because they share a kind, but because we can apply the same concept to both.”

So perhaps the only commonality between God and the world is that neither is absolute nothingness. That’s it. Even that shared concept is more linguistic than ontological.

God, then, remains wholly Other.


A Second Deductive Path

  1. The universe had an absolute beginning.

  2. Such a beginning must originate in God.

  3. So the universe originates in God.

  4. God can only create from His own substance (i.e. creatio ex Deo).

  5. Thus, the universe is the transformation of divine essence into worldly immanence.

  6. God’s total transformation is not impossible.

  7. Whatever God creates will follow a necessary causal and/or teleological path. This means:

    • The principle of sufficient reason underlies everything.

    • There are no true alternatives.

    • Determinism (and/or finalism) governs all action.

    • Human actions also follow the nature from which they come. (agere sequitur esse)

  8. Therefore, creation is bound to necessity.

  9. It is irrational for a perfectly wise God to coexist with a wholly necessary world. Why?

    • A deterministic universe would make divine oversight absurd or redundant.

    • If everything happens necessarily, God’s role becomes meaningless.

    • Even paradise, if it arises through process, is unnecessary for an omnipotent being. He could have created it immediately (Mainländer).

→ D. Hence, God did not coexist with His creation.
He became it. Entirely.


The Third Deduction: God’s Ontological Self-Emptying

  1. God has transformed Himself either into:
    (x) a temporally finite universe, or
    (y) a temporally infinite and ever-moving one.

1.1 If (y) – an ever-moving universe – is the case:

Then God has become something ontologically inferior to His original state. Even if the universe were eternal and timeless, it would still be a fragmented multiplicity — a far cry from the original perfect unity of divine being.

(i) However, God’s perfect wisdom (even understood analogically) would prohibit an irreversible self-subordination to a lesser form of existence. God would not permanently enter into an inferior state of being.

1.2 If (x) – a temporally finite universe – is the case:

Then the universe either ends in:
a) a miraculous reconstitution of the “dead” God (who would remain unchanged and gain nothing from the process), or
b) in absolute nothingness (nihil negativum).

(ii) But God does nothing in vain — no superfluous or purposeless act can be attributed to Him.


2. Therefore, God's essence has been transformed into a plurality of individual forces, each unconsciously striving toward a shared final goal: non-existence — a kind of metaphysical nirvāna. This state is not to be confused with a possible world. It is, rather, the total absence of God, the universe, and any conceivable world — a creatio ad nihilum.

Some might object: “But isn’t nothingness itself just another possible world — an empty one?”

Yet as David Bentley Hart rightly clarifies:

“An empty world, conceived as merely one possible state of reality among others, is not nonexistence, but only a kind of existing thing devoid of qualities (whatever that might mean).”
The Experience of God: Being, Consciousness, Bliss

True nothingness is not an alternative reality. It is the absolute negation of all possible realities.


Divine Simplicity and the Necessity of Becoming

I.

Mainländer writes:

“God did not have the power not to be all at once.”

In other words, God could not immediately eliminate Himself without leaving behind some trace of His having existed — a metaphysical residue of His “having-been-ness”. Therefore, absolute nothingness required an intermediate state — a temporally extended process of self-dissolution.

II.

Why this delay?

“Where something existed of itself, it cannot immediately become nothing.”
Thorsten Lerchner (on Mainländer)

God’s essence — pure being, absolute givenness, unconditioned subsistence — is the most real and dense form of existence conceivable. That kind of being resists immediate annihilation by its very nature. Mainländer's God, like the God of classical theism, is absolutely simpleesse per se subsistens — existing through and in Himself, not derived from anything else.

Subsistence implies Simplicity and vice versa:

“God is simple because composition always implies conditionality, causation, actualisation of potentiality and a non-identity of the parts with the whole.”
Thomas Marschner

Thus, divine simplicity — a metaphysical precondition for absolute subsistence — becomes the very reason God cannot spontaneously annihilate Himself.

As Anthony K. Jensen notes:

“God’s own essence as Übersein was the obstacle that precluded at least the instantaneous execution of the one pre-worldly act.”
The Death and Redemption of God

God’s omnipotence, then, is not omnipotent with respect to Himself:

“God’s power was omnipotent in that nothing outside of Him constrained it. But it was no omnipotence with respect to His own power. The simple unity was unable, by means of itself, to cease to exist.”
Mainländer, synkretic.com/issues/the-philosophy-of-redemption


III.

Therefore, God had no option (even if only analogously speaking) but to become a universe in decay — a world destined for total entropy and eventual non-being.

God, the Non-Finite, had to become finite, so that the finite could, in turn, dissolve into nothingness. There was no alternative path.

No divine sustainer is needed. God does not remain behind the scenes to maintain the cosmos. The “suicidal explosion” of divine being was also the first and final act of creation.

Creation persists temporarily due to the residual divine power that animates it — a slowly depleting inheritance stored in the very structure of things:

“The first impulse still lives on.”
Mainländer

This is elaborated by Lerchner:

“Finite things are temporarily self-sustaining because they draw on the bundled remains of the dead deity.”

This also explains why the universe does not collapse instantly: everything is, for a time, still “running on divine fumes.”

In Mainländer’s metaphysics, God initially had no will, only a pure state of simple being. The moment the will to non-existence arises, He ceases to be. The act of willing and the transformation of God into the universe are one and the same event. Due to His simplicity, it cannot be otherwise.

“God cannot help but transform Himself into His will to nothingness.”

This will is not non-being itself — it is the drive toward it, which manifests as the world. Hence, the world is God’s metaphysical suicide in slow motion. Metaphorically understood as God as the decaying world.


All Things Strive for Nothingness

According to Mainländer, all things — all matter, all forces — strive toward non-being, but they impede each other from reaching that goal. In a paradoxical way, we are held in existence not by a benevolent deity but by mutual obstruction.

Consider gravity, for example:

“Gravity does not cease its striving toward an unextended central point, though to reach it would be to negate itself and all matter.”
Schopenhauer, echoed by Mainländer

If anything were to reach the precise center of gravitational pull, it would be compressed to an extensionless, motionless point — total annihilation. Gravity, thus, is a force not of unity but of self-erasure.

Anthony K. Jensen summarizes this well:

“Matter is a conglomerate of forces which, if not resisted by counterforces, would immediately self-annihilate.”
The Death and Redemption of God

In other words: existence survives by mutual resistance to annihilation.


Black Holes: Cosmic Symbols of This Striving

Even physicists describe black holes in terms that echo Mainländer's vision:

“They always win in the end... it’s Death triumphant.”
Gregory Benford

“It’s this monstrous, mysterious thing... that eats everything.”
Andrew Hamilton

“Whatever falls in is no longer accessible to our world.”
Brian McNamara

Black holes are the closest physical analogue to Mainländer’s metaphysical vision: the hunger of reality for non-being.


Final Note:

For Mainländer, there is no second world, no afterlife, no resurrection. When something is lost, it is truly lost. No divine memory preserves it. No metaphysical archive stores it. What has perished, perished utterly.

Fourth Deduction: On Divine Freedom and the Will to Non-Existence

This deduction serves as a supplement to the previous arguments by focusing on the divine act of free will that led to creation, not as a fulfillment of purpose or expression of lack, but as an intentional self-abnegation.


Fifth Deduction.

I. God as the Most Perfect Being

God (analogically speaking) exists as the most perfect and blissful being:

“We can conceive of no more complete and better being than that of a simple unity.”
Philipp Mainländer
synkretic.com/issues/the-philosophy-of-redemption

This perfect simplicity entails an existence of timeless bliss — “happily static and statically happy,” in the words of Bertrand R. Brasnett:

“If the Eternal be conceived as in complete and perfect bliss, happily static and statically happy, there is no reason in logic or in life why he should ever be moved to engage in creation.”
The Suffering of the Impassible God

II. The Paradox of Divine Freedom

Mainländer holds that God possessed true libertarian freedom: the absolute ability to either remain in eternal supra-existence or to end that existence altogether.

Importantly, continuing to exist is not a “decision” in the usual sense — supra-existence is already given. The decision to remain is not a positive act but the absence of willing non-being. Hence, the only genuine exercise of freedom is to will the cessation of existence.

“Only one deed was possible for God — one truly free deed, because He was under no compulsion: to enter absolute nothingness, the nihil negativum, i.e., to annihilate Himself completely.”
Mainländer

III. The Only Reason for Creation

If God were ever to create, it could not be to gain anything, since He lacks nothing. Therefore:

Creation can only be the means by which God ceases to be.

Since non-being cannot be achieved directly — due to the nature of divine simplicity and ontological fullness — it must be approached through temporality, via a mediated process. Thus, creation is not an end in itself, but a necessary detour toward absolute annihilation.

IV. The World as a Sign of Divine Will to Die

The universe — the sum of all dynamic individual beings — is the “medium” through which God enacts His willed self-dissolution. Despite His perfection and untroubled bliss, He chooses — from a position of pure freedom and self-sufficiency, entirely unpressured by inner or outer conditions — non-being.

This will to non-existence is not human self-denial projected onto God. It infinitely transcends human categories of moral or emotional self-sacrifice.

“So why the primal unity fractured itself, why the One became many, remains a mystery for us.”
Frederick C. Beiser, Weltschmerz

This is one of the very few justified appeals to mystery — not because the decision was irrational, but because genuine metaphysical freedom is inherently opaque to finite minds.

“There is an arbitrary dimension to choices that are free in the libertarian sense.”
Kronen & Reitan, God's Final Victory

God, being utterly alone, could only be moved by Himself, from within His own simplicity.

Divine Freedom and Logical Consistency

Some philosophers have noted that a perfect being cannot lack anything and therefore cannot be motivated to create. Theodore Drange states:

“To deliberately create anything requires some sort of lack, and that is incompatible with being a perfect being.”
Nonbelief & Evil

Mainländer confirms this insight — with a twist:

  • If creation cannot result from lack, it must stem from an absolute, free decision to cease to be.

  • Therefore, God creates only in order to annihilate Himself, not to fulfill a purpose or desire.

This is not a defect in His being. A perfect being cannot improve; thus, choosing non-existence is not a sign of deficiency but of radical sovereignty.


Does Ceasing to Exist Indicate Greater Perfection?

One might argue that the exercise of freedom — especially the act of willing non-being — is a higher perfection than merely existing in a state of passive bliss. But this creates paradoxes:

  • Perfection is traditionally linked to being, not non-being.

  • The act of freely choosing to cease to be negates that perfection.

  • If freedom is highest when exercised, then God must exercise it. But then, His freedom necessitates His self-destruction — which is a contradiction.

Hence, God’s act cannot be judged by human standards of what constitutes “greater perfection.”


Objections and Their Limits

Even if one rejects Mainländer’s theology, objections often misunderstand the radical nature of divine simplicity. His God is not Thomistic. He does not necessarily will Himself. He is not the Good Itself, but a Being who can choose to reject even Himself.

The Catholic dogma — that God necessarily wills Himself and only wills others freely — is inverted here. Mainländer’s God can suspend even that necessity.

Thus, God may indulge in perfect self-love and still rationally conclude:

It is better not to be — not for lack, not for sorrow, but from an uncompelled realization that non-being is preferable to even perfect being.


Application to Human Suicide?

David Bentley Hart once wrote:

“One cannot even choose nothingness, at least not as nothingness; to will nonexistence positively, one must first conceive it as a positive end... in the end, even when we reject the good, we always do so out of a longing for the Good.”
That All Shall Be Saved

But applied to God, this logic breaks down. Mainländer’s God does not long for “the Good.” He is or better was the Good from our perspective — and yet denies it. The act of willing non-being is not disguised longing but authentic metaphysical judgment. We cannot impose anthropocentric frameworks on this divine act.


Final Reflection

Mainländer’s theology presents a radical alternative to classical theism:

  • God does not will Himself necessarily.

  • He can freely generate a will.

  • That will can choose annihilation.

  • Creation is not an act of fulfillment but of termination.

God does not cease to exist because of a lack but because He freely chose that it is better not to exist at all.

Further Supplement: On Divine Will, Pantheism, and the Fragmentation of Unity

I. A Critique of Classical Theism and the Goodness of God

The following critique, raised by Jeffrey D. Johnson, strikes at the metaphysical core of Thomistic theology:

“How is it possible for God to will his own existence by the same undifferentiated and timeless act of willing the universe without the universe being eternal and necessary?”
The Failure of Natural Theology

This question highlights a tension within classical theism: If God’s act of will is timeless and singular, and that act includes the willing of creation, then creation must also be co-eternal and necessary. But that would collapse the distinction between God and the world — a pantheistic implication.

The same tension emerges when theologians assert that God is goodness itself. As Anthony Kenny observes:

“Unlike the predicate ‘blue’, ‘good’ is an attributive adjective: one can be a good doctor or a good knife, but not good in the abstract. To claim that God is ‘pure goodness’ ignores the linguistic structure of the word ‘good’, introduced by Plato and heavily criticized by Aristotle. It is strange to see this Platonic notion survive in Aquinas’s Aristotelian system.”
Christianity in Review: A History of the Faith in Fifty Books

II. Mainländer’s Alternative: The God Who Chose Not to Be

Mainländer's God could not “improve” or become “more Godly”; He already encompassed all possibility. Hence, His only true decision was the one Hamlet faced: to remain as He was, or not to be.

“Why God made the choice He did is ungraspable, but the result, evident in the world today, is transcendental proof of which path was taken. God willed not to be.”
Anthony K. Jensen, The Death and Redemption of God

Freedom to cease to exist must, then, be included in divine perfection. God, in this conception, may be imagined — anthropomorphically — as a being who, through absolute self-reflection, recognizes the vanity of existence, even His own. Nothing remains hidden to such a being; everything, including Himself, appears as surface. And in this realization, He grows weary of being.

This leads to a figurative interpretation: If existential reflection is a sign of human depth, then it must, in divine potentiation, be even more profound in God. God is the ultimate existential philosopher — not despairing, not depressed, but serenely and wisely sacrificing Himself for a metaphysical good: non-being.


Sixth Deduction: Against Pantheism and Toward Finite Individuality

I. The world originated from a unique, supreme being endowed with ultimate power and wisdom (even if only analogously).

II. The world is a creation — the product of this being’s intentional act.

III. The world cannot be a pantheistic manifestation of God. In pantheism:

“The individual is nothing — a mere puppet of a Being hidden in the world… no act is truly theirs, no responsibility truly borne.”
Mainländer

Pantheism fails to account for the reality of individual subjectivity. As Mainländer stresses, the individuation we experience is not mere illusion or appearance (à la Kant) but an essential feature of reality.

IV. Three Arguments Against Pantheism

1. The Reality of Individuality

The sheer inner richness of our experience — appetite, resistance, will, spontaneity, agency — refutes the pantheistic claim that we are mere modifications of a single being. Individual subjectivity cannot be an illusion:

Cogito ergo sum — even the illusion of subjectivity requires a subject.

If we are entirely dependent on another being (as in pantheism or strong scholastic theism), we collapse into that being. As Bill Vallicella puts it:

“If the creature is dependent on God both for its existence and for its nature, the creature collapses into God.”
Maverick Philosopher

Thus, true individuality — observed all throughout nature — cannot be reduced to mere modes of one infinite subject.

2. Logical Incoherence of Simultaneous Unity and Multiplicity

Mainländer criticizes Schopenhauer’s version of pantheism for claiming that the One Will can be wholly present in a fly and wholly present in a human being at the same time — a claim that violates the law of non-contradiction:

“Simple unity is utterly incompatible with multiplicity, if both are to exist at the same time.”

Multiplicity of manifestation is only possible sequentially, not simultaneously. A fully simple will cannot exhaust itself multiple times at once.

3. Theodicy and Divine Intelligence

Schopenhauer’s critique of pantheism applies here as well:

“It would be an ill-advised God who transformed Himself into this cruel world — filled with hunger, suffering, slavery, factory misery, and meaningless violence. Such a being would hardly qualify as ‘all-wise’.”
Parerga and Paralipomena, Vol. II, §69

But in Mainländer’s model, the situation is radically different: God is dead. There is no deity remaining to bear responsibility for suffering. The divine act was a metaphysical suicide, and the world is the slow unfolding of that death.

In this sense, every being took part in that original decision. Each individual willed its own fate, within the singular pre-worldly unity:

“Everything that affects me... I willed it. Not gradually, but in the primal act, within the divine unity, I determined that it should affect me.”
Mainländer


Ethical Consequences: Living with a Dead God

While suffering is real and widespread, there remains a path of voluntary simplicity aligned with the divine trajectory toward dissolution:

The ethical ideal is the “Holy Spirit” — a life of sexual abstinence and voluntary poverty. This path harmonizes with the divine course of nature and avoids the agonistic striving of “Satanic” hedonism.


VI–X. Final Synthesis: From Divine Unity to Living Individuals

VI. Classical theism and pantheism ultimately converge. Despite surface differences, both reduce the individual to an expression of divine being.

VII. But the world is a multiplicity of real individuals — not modes, not shadows.

VIII. Hence, God cannot have chosen to continue existing or to merely modify His mode of being, or else the world would never have come into existence.

“He cannot have chosen to exist as a super-being alongside His creation.”
Sebastian Gardner

IX. Therefore, God must have fragmented Himself, metaphorically speaking, into a multiplicity of real, finite, individual forces.

X. This fragmentation was not a mere internal complexification of God’s being (as in deus sive natura), but a literal disintegration into multiple things-in-themselves — a shattering of the One into the Many.

“The disintegration of simple unity into a world of multiplicity... all subsequent movements are merely further fragmentation.”
Mainländer


Conclusion of the Deductions

Instead of a dead individual and a living God, we have living individuals and a dead God.

This is Mainländer’s metaphysical inversion of classical and pantheistic theologies. Creation was not a glorious emergence of finite beings from a transcendent source, but a deliberate act of self-nullification. The divine chose non-being, and in doing so, became the world, which now moves inevitably toward dissolution — not because it is cursed, but because it was born of a sacrifice.

Supplementary Reflections on Creatio ex Deo in Light of Mainländer’s Philosophy

To further clarify and strengthen the plausibility of creation from God’s own being (creatio ex Deo) within the framework of Mainländer’s metaphysical system, we can draw upon a set of recent philosophical reflections that challenge the coherence of creatio ex nihilo and lend support to an alternative model — one remarkably compatible with Mainländer’s.


I. Four Contemporary Reflections on Creatio ex Deo

(1) W. P. Swainson (on Jacob Böhme):

“The Supreme does not create out of nothing. Ex nihilo nihil fit — out of nothing, nothing comes. He produces from His own eternal nature and eternal wisdom, wherein all things dwell in a latent condition, all contrasts exist in a hidden or non-manifest state.”
Jacob Boehme: The Teutonic Philosopher

(2) Maverick Philosopher (Bill Vallicella):

“Classical theists hold that God created the world ex nihilo, out of nothing. [...] But if God creates out of nothing distinct from himself, this allows that, in some sense, God creates ex Deo, out of himself. In this way, creatio ex nihilo and ex nihilo nihil fit can be reconciled.”

This formulation acknowledges the intuitive appeal of the Principle of Pre-existent Stuff (PPS): that nothing can come from nothing, and therefore some metaphysical substance or ground must pre-exist creation. If nothing is distinct from God, then the only possible metaphysical material is God Himself.

(3) Daniel Soars (on Aquinas):

“If the world emerges neither from sheer nothingness nor from any pre-existent some-thing, it must emerge ex Deo — from God. [...] Aquinas rejects this conclusion, but only by denying that God can serve as a ‘material cause’. Yet if we abstract from materiality as ‘physical stuff’, it seems legitimate to call God the innermost cause — the substantial ground — of the creature.”

This argument shows that creatio ex Deo is not metaphysically incompatible with Aquinas’s system, provided one rethinks the notion of material cause as immaterial substance or ontological ground.

(4) Michael Tze-Sung Longenecker:

“The Pre-existent Stuff Principle (PSP) has intuitive force: for anything that begins to exist, there must be stuff out of which it is made. [...] If the universe began to exist, the pre-existent stuff must be non-physical and immaterial. [...] Christians cannot posit any distinct eternal material; therefore, the only coherent option left is that God created the universe out of Himself.”


II. Mainländer’s God and the Logic of Creatio ex Deo

These reflections dovetail remarkably with Mainländer’s metaphysical theology, wherein God does not create from nothing but from His own being. For Mainländer:

  • God is absolutely simple and indivisible.

  • No part of Him can be separated and externalized.

  • Therefore, the act of creating is necessarily the act of entire self-transformation: God becomes the world.

  • The world is not His artifact; it is His corpse — the structured remains of a God who willed not to be.

This makes Mainländer’s system a radical and coherent form of creatio ex Deo, one in which divine self-annihilation is the metaphysical condition for the world’s becoming.


III. Plotinus and the Ancient Barrier to Divine Self-Nullification

In contrast to Mainländer, Plotinus — and with him much of ancient and late antique philosophy — insisted that the One could give rise to multiplicity without losing anything of itself:

“Somehow, everything is in the One, but there it is totally indistinct and undifferentiated.”
Eyjólfur K. Emilsson, Plotinus

Plotinus's solution lies in the emanation model: the One radiates being without diminishing itself — like the sun shining while remaining full. But this was not a proof, only a dogmatic metaphysical axiom rooted in what might be called a cognitive prohibition: the thought that the highest principle could perish was, for ancient thinkers, unspeakable.

This dogma resembles what German poet Christian Morgenstern mocked as:

“Weil nicht sein kann, was nicht sein darf.”
(“What must not be, cannot be.”)

Mainländer’s system boldly transgresses this barrier. If the One is absolute simplicity, then it cannot produce otherness without ceasing to be itself. All differentiation must occur within, and if simplicity excludes internal structure, then the act of self-fragmentation entails total dissolution of the source.


IV. From Undifferentiated to Differentiated: A Necessity of Loss

Let us then pose a revised principle:

If everything in the One is indistinct and undifferentiated, and if a real world of distinction and differentiation is to emerge, then that differentiation must occur within the One itself, leading to the loss of simplicity, and hence, the loss of the One.

This directly affirms Mainländer’s proposition:

“God is dead, and His death was the life of the world.”

The differentiated world is the manifestation of God's lost simplicity — not a mere appearance, but the real consequence of the One’s absolute dissolution.


V. Summary and Philosophical Implication

The creatio ex Deo model — as developed through both contemporary critique and Mainländer’s metaphysics — offers a radical but coherent alternative to classical theism and its reliance on creatio ex nihilo:

  • Ex nihilo nihil fit holds as a metaphysical principle.

  • The only non-arbitrary way to honor it is to accept that creation must proceed from the only existing metaphysical ground: God Himself.

  • But if God is simple and indivisible, creation is not emanation but self-shattering.

  • The world is thus the mortal residue of divine self-negation.

In short:

The world exists not because God wanted to manifest His glory, but because He willed His own extinction. Creation is not the act of a living God, but the lingering echo of a God who chose not to be.

Supplements: Divine Simplicity, Self-Limitation, and the Ontological Collapse of God

I. From Self-Determination to Self-Destruction

The notion that God's existence portions itself by means of self-determination and self-limitation, resulting in the immediate emergence of created beings, seems, at first glance, compatible with traditional metaphysical models of emanation or divine will. However, once we accept two key premises — that God is both infinite (non-finite) and absolutely simple — the logical outcome of this self-limitation becomes clear: God cannot divide Himself without remainder.

Hence, God's self-limitation is also His total annihilation.

Why?

Because if God is simplicity itself, then any finite mode of being must necessarily arise from a total transformation of that simplicity. No partial manifestation is metaphysically possible. The simple cannot limit itself partially, only absolutely — a point strongly echoed in classical sources.

“For comprehending all in itself, [God] contains existence itself as an infinite and indeterminate sea of substance.”
John Damascene (cited in Aquinas, ST I.13.11)

This image of the infinite sea offers a helpful metaphor: it is not a sea with boundaries or location, but a spaceless fullness. If one draws from it even a single finite thing, the whole is transformed. There can be only one act of drawing — and that act drains the sea entirely.


II. The Logical End of Divine Simplicity: The Vanishing One

Thus, in the words of Sebastian Gardner, we must conceive of:

“A vanished One possessed of absolute simple individuality,”
or
“a One which is transcendent, pre-mundane, and defunct.”

God’s act of creation is simultaneously His disappearance. To create, in this model, is not to emanate or project, but to transform fully into otherness.

This provides a coherent metaphysical explanation of the transformation of the absolute unity into the world of multiplicity — a transformation not of expression, but of substitution: the world is what remains after God is gone.


III. David Bentley Hart and the Limits of Classical Theism

Consider a set of reflections by David Bentley Hart in The Experience of God: Being, Consciousness, Bliss. Hart illustrates the traditional metaphor of creation by subtraction:

“Created things exist by subtraction: that is, they are finite and diffuse expressions of an infinite and indivisible reality... God is the infinite ‘ocean of being,’ while creatures are finite vessels containing existence only in limited measure.”

But Hart’s language subtly betrays the deeper implication of what he resists: if things come into being by subtracting from God — if creation occurs by God limiting His plenitude — then we are already on the threshold of creatio ex Deo.

Hart attempts to safeguard divine immutability and untouchability:

“Nothing is added to God by creation; all finite things are already embraced in God’s being in a more eminent way.”

But this raises a contradiction. If something finite “emerges”, it must do so through a loss of undivided simplicity. Hart’s final retreat into mystery“Si comprehendis, non est Deus” — cannot conceal the plausibility of divine alteration, which his metaphors inadvertently support.


IV. The Ontological Problem of Divine Modulation

Hart’s reluctance to affirm divine transformation leads to conceptual instability. If we ask:

How could divine simplicity “modulate” itself without ceasing to be simple?

— the answer is: It cannot.

If God is truly simple, then any modulation — even the slightest — amounts to ontological rupture. There is no gradual self-expression for a simple being; only all or nothing.

This brings us back to a Mainländerian formulation:

The act of self-determination is the act of self-abolition.


V. A Stronger Alternative: Seven Propositions in Defense of Total Divine Transformation

  1. There exists a metaphysical state in which God alone is — ontologically prior to all creation.

  2. The universe began to exist — the past is finite.

  3. A finite past implies a first temporal effect, which must originate from a non-temporal cause — namely, God.

  4. God is unity itself, i.e., absolute simplicity.

  5. All possible creation exists undifferentiated in God prior to creation.

  6. Creatio ex nihilo is incoherent; therefore, creation must be ex Deo.

  7. But if creation occurs from the simple God, then the act alters God, and due to simplicity, any alteration is total. Therefore, creation equals God’s annihilation.


VI. Whether God Has Parts or Not: Either Way, He Perishes

Even if we concede, contrary to simplicity, that God has parts, the outcome is the same. As Michael Tze-Sung Longenecker notes in A Theory of Creation Ex Deo:

“If God creates the universe out of His proper parts, then He loses the functions or features those parts confer. If even the smallest part is missing, the whole perishes.”

Creation is therefore always an act of loss — and for a perfect, self-sufficient being, even a small loss is incompatible with divinity.

Whether partless or composite, any donation of being on God’s part leads to His own undoing.


VII. Mainländer’s Apparent Reference to Divine Parts

At times, Mainländer seems to imply internal distinction within God — e.g., between “supra-essence” and “supra-being”. Yet this duality is not a real composition, but a conceptual distinction for human understanding. Absent this, God would be indistinguishable from absolute nothingness.

So even if conceptual duality aids human comprehension, it still leads to the same conclusion: once a part of God is transformed or sacrificed, God as a unified being no longer exists.


VIII. Schopenhauer and the Impossibility of Created Freedom

A further philosophical consequence is that God cannot create free beings — a conclusion drawn by Schopenhauer, which supports Mainländer's metaphysical logic:

“To create a free being would require giving it existence without essence — an impossibility.”
Parerga and Paralipomena, Vol. I, §§9, 13

To act follows from being (agere sequitur esse). If a being is created, its constitution is determined. Hence, no creature can be truly free, and the creator cannot avoid responsibility for its actions.

Thus, we might say:

God’s freedom precedes His being — not the other way around.

In Mainländer’s system, God was originally without will — He became willing only once, and that will was the will to not be.


IX. Final Consequence: Creation as Sacrificial Self-Negation

From the totality of these arguments, we arrive at the following:

  • Creation is not expression but annihilation.

  • Finite things exist only because God ceases to be.

  • Whether God is simple or composed, the act of giving birth to otherness is fatal.

  • There is no remaining deity behind the world. God died in becoming the world.

This brings us back to Mainländer’s boldest thesis, now grounded in contemporary metaphysical critique and classical metaphysical language:

The universe is the corpse of God.
The world exists because the divine chose not glory, not expression, but dissolution.

Supplement VII: Divine Necessity, Human Freedom, and the Final Collapse of Classical Theism

I. The Inescapable Burden of Theodicy and Divine Responsibility

Schopenhauer underscores a deep and unresolved problem: if God is the creator of all things, then He is also the creator of the conditions for evil. As early as Augustine, this tension was recognized with philosophical honesty:

“Tell me, pray, whether God is not the author of evil?”
Augustine, On Free Will

Later, Luther forcefully echoed this deterministic dilemma:

“If we grant that God is omniscient and omnipotent, then it follows obviously and incontestably that we did not create ourselves [...] but only through His omnipotence.”
Schopenhauer, Essay on the Freedom of the Will

Hence, if all things, including the human will, arise from divine omnipotence, then the will itself becomes a function of divine necessity — an extension of God’s own determination.


II. The Feser Analogy: Fictional Freedom and its Collapse

Edward Feser, a proponent of classical theism, attempts to preserve human freedom through analogy:

“Characters in a novel act freely within the story, even though the author writes all their actions.”

This analogy, however, collapses under scrutiny. As Gunther Laird points out:

  • Fictional characters appear to have freedom only within the narrative frame.

  • But they do not possess ontological freedom; they are wholly subject to the author’s will.

  • Therefore, if the world is God's narrative, our supposed freedom is fictionala simulation, not reality.

To say we are free within a story authored by God is to admit that, from the standpoint of metaphysical reality, we are not truly free at all.


III. The Principle of Sufficient Reason (PSR) and the Necessity of Determinism

Even Feser insists on the universality of the PSR:

“To reject the PSR is to undermine the possibility of any rational inquiry.”
Five Proofs of the Existence of God

But if PSR holds universally, then it must apply also to the human will. As Fichte (via Neuhouser) and Schopenhauer argue:

“If we can always find a reason for the will’s choice, we demonstrate that the opposite action was not possible. Therefore, the will is not free.”

There cannot be uncaused choices within a rational system that also affirms PSR. Hence, the very structure of reason entails that freedom of will is an illusion.

“To a given man under given circumstances, are two actions possible, or only one? The answer of all who think deeply: only one.”
Schopenhauer, Freedom of the Will


IV. The Collapse of Volitional Indeterminacy: Hart and the Illusion of Hell

David Bentley Hart, despite his theological commitments, admits this much:

“There must be a ‘why’ in any free choice — a sufficient reason.”

If true, then freedom collapses into rational necessity. No sane, informed, and rational agent could freely choose eternal misery over beatific union with God.

Therefore, the notion of hell as a free choice is incoherent:

“To call that madness ‘freedom’ [...] is to talk gibberish.”
Hart, The Obscenity of Hell

So either:

  • Free choice does not exist,

  • Or if it does, its conditions are never satisfied.

In both cases, libertarian freedom is impossible.


V. Biblical Fatalism: The Mouse and the Cat

The Bible itself affirms divine determinism repeatedly:

  • Jeremiah 10:23: “It is not in man who walks to direct his steps.”

  • Romans 9:16: “It depends not on human will or exertion, but on God.”

  • Exodus 4:21: “I will harden Pharaoh’s heart.”

This view inspired Mainländer’s metaphor:

“The individual is like a mouse created by the cat (God), which then toys with it until she bites off its head.”

In this image, human agency is reduced to performance within a divine theater, fated, controlled, and ultimately discarded.


VI. The Mistaken Assumption of Eternal Divine Will

Western theism has long assumed that the Perfect Being must will to exist eternally. But this is a value judgment, not a logical necessity.

  • Nothing prevents God from "concluding" (timelessly) that non-being is preferable.

  • Absolute nothingness may not possess any qualities, but for a perfect being, it may still be the "better" negationa final act of value-based self-negation.

This introduces the possibility of a divine decision for death, a metaphysical suicide that is not irrational, but sovereign.


VII. Buddhism, Christianity, and Philosophical Suicide

Even Buddhism, which now enjoys significant global influence, echoes this shift:

“The definition of Nirvana shifted from being merged with ultimate reality to extinction.”
Yancey & Quosigk

And Christianity, paradoxically, flirts with the same idea in the death of Christ:

“[Jesus] is the cause of His own death [...] His suicide is built into the Christian story.”
Jack Miles, Christ: A Crisis in the Life of God

The logic of self-willed divine death runs as an underground current even in the heart of Christian theology.


VIII. Cosmological Arguments Do Not Require God’s Continued Existence

Philosophers such as George Smith, Peter Cole, and Peter Forrest argue persuasively:

  • Cosmological arguments may show that God once existed.

  • But they do not entail that God still exists.

“There is no reason to assume that the first cause still exists.”
Smith, Atheism: The Case Against God

“Why should God not be the originator and now no longer exist?”
Cole, Philosophy of Religion

Even Hume speculates:

“This world is the production of old age and dotage in some superannuated deity.”


IX. Developmental Theism: Necessary Existence as Initial, Not Eternal

Peter Forrest’s “developmental theism” provides a helpful framework:

  • God necessarily exists at the first moment of time.

  • Time itself may begin with God's initial act.

  • But nothing logically prohibits God from ceasing to exist thereafter.

“There is nothing incoherent in the idea that a simple being might cease to exist.”
Forrest, Developmental Theism

This opens the door to a Mainländerian view of divinity: a necessary beginning that chooses not to persist.


X. The Philosophical and Scientific Advantage of Mainländer’s God

Mainländer’s model offers several profound advantages:

  • Eliminates transcendental intrusion into immanence.

  • Fits perfectly with entropy: the universe is in progressive decay because its origin is an act of dissolution.

  • Unifies cosmology with teleology: entropy is not chaotic but purposeful in its drive toward nothingness.

“Entropy is a teleological process.”
Intelligent Design sources, ironically aligned with Mainländer

Mainländer’s system offers the investigator of nature a clean metaphysical slate, as he says:

“I consider the pure, immanent domain, totally freed from the spectre of transcendent essentialities, to be a second gift that I am making to the investigators of nature.”
Mainländer, Philosophy of Redemption


XI. God as Contingent Termination: The Final Image

Mainländer’s God or Simple Unity:

  • Is not “personal” in the human sense, nor impersonal like a rock.

  • Transcends all categories, but analogically closer to a person.

  • Is free in the highest possible sense: the ability to annihilate itself without compulsion.

  • Exists necessarily in all possible worlds as the starting point, but not as an eternal presence.

  • Is contingent not in its origin, but in its willed whither.

This God is the source of all, but also the first to choose non-being. Not out of despair, but from a sovereign and freely chosen affirmation that the best thing to do with perfection is to relinquish it.


Edward Feser and the Perverted Faculty Argument: A Critical Anthology

Overview of the Perverted Faculty Argument The perverted faculty argument asserts that the sole morally permissible use of the sexual facult...